STRANGERS IN OUR MIDST
The Political Philosophy of Immigration
David Miller
Harvard University
584 pages; $35
DEFECTIVES IN THE LAND
Disability and Immigration in the Age of Eugenics
Douglas C. Baynton
University of Chicago
584 pages; $35
CITY OF GODS
Religious Freedom, Immigration, and Pluralism in Flushing, Queens
R Scott Hanson
Empire State Editions/Fordham University
584 pages; $35
From Hobbes and Hegel to John Stuart Mill and John Rawls, the seminal figures of Western political theory are united in their almost complete neglect of immigration. No doubt they have their reasons. Who among them witnessed anything like the global refugee crisis of 2015? Or the anxieties about national identity that it inflamed? Be that as it may, with hostility toward immigrants and refugees fueling the "Brexit" movement and the presidential campaign of Donald Trump, we could use some deep thinking about the relationship between the state and its citizens.
On the case is the political philosopher David Miller. His book Strangers in Our Midst: The Political Philosophy of Immigration aims to be the first to combine such an abstract approach to the topic with such a strong dose of realism. Make no mistake: Mr Miller is a humane, social democratic Oxford University professor. But comes down in favour of a state's right - except when human rights are threatened - to close its borders to outsiders, and proposes four principles that should govern policies while admitting immigrants.
The first principle is what he calls "weak cosmopolitanism." A weak cosmopolitan believes in the equal worth of all human beings but sees this as morally compatible with giving special consideration to our compatriots. The argument is simple: The radical changes to our behaviour required by a strong cosmopolitanism - which holds that we have an obligation to treat all people the same - would entail abandoning too much of what gives shape and meaning to our lives.
In the context of immigration, strong cosmopolitanism mandates an international "open borders" policy, whereas weak cosmopolitanism dictates only that a country's policy cannot violate anyone's human rights and sometimes must actively protect them.
Mr Miller's second principle is national self-determination. Immigration can bring about considerable change to a country, and Mr Miller argues that citizens have the right to decide whether such changes would bolster or undermine their society. Any such policies have to be consistent with weak cosmopolitanism - and also, Mr Miller believes, with his third principle: fairness. The aim of a state's immigration policy has to be one that would-be immigrants ought to accept as reasonable.
Does that seem as if it might get blurry in practice? The early history of immigration policy in America, as told by historian Douglas C Baynton in Defectives In The Land: Disability And Immigration In The Age Of Eugenics suggests so. Traditionally, scholars have divided that history into two periods: a "selective" phase starting in 1882, which involved screening out individuals with any "defect" that would render them "likely to become a public charge"; and a "restrictive phase" starting with the passage of a literacy test in 1917.
Yet Mr Baynton, challenging conventional historiography, argues that the selective phase, despite its reliance on the "public charge" standard, was no less discriminatory. During those years, he demonstrates, immigration officials could and did customarily invoke this to rule out such "defectives" as women unaccompanied by male providers and members of races with supposed "predispositions" to criminality.
The fourth of Mr Miller's principles is social integration, where Mr Miller calls for certain commitments, as well as a certain flexibility, on the part of everyone involved.
Mr Miller argues for reciprocity with respect to cultural integration. A Muslim immigrant to Italy, he feels, should not object to the presence of a crucifix in his daughter's classroom as a symbol of the nation's Catholic heritage; but neither should her school object to her preference for modest dress and the wearing of a head scarf. Here, too, the American example is relevant. In his minutely detailed City Of Gods the historian R Scott Hanson uses the story of Flushing - which calls itself the birthplace of religious freedom in America and is now the hub of the most religiously diverse large county in the US - as a "case study" of the promises and drawbacks of pluralism. How religiously diverse can a society get?
Mr Hanson, who has also done ethnographic work in the neighbourhood, concludes there is virtually "no limit" to how much religious diversity a society can accommodate. But he also finds that when it comes to cooperation and unity - two goals that Mr Miller, at least, places considerable emphasis on - there are limits to how much of a sense of community you can achieve in such a pluralistic environment. It's another consideration to bear in mind for those who seek to respect social cohesion as well as the rights and interests of prospective immigrants.
©2016 The New York Times News service
The Political Philosophy of Immigration
David Miller
Harvard University
584 pages; $35
More From This Section
Disability and Immigration in the Age of Eugenics
Douglas C. Baynton
University of Chicago
584 pages; $35
CITY OF GODS
Religious Freedom, Immigration, and Pluralism in Flushing, Queens
R Scott Hanson
Empire State Editions/Fordham University
584 pages; $35
From Hobbes and Hegel to John Stuart Mill and John Rawls, the seminal figures of Western political theory are united in their almost complete neglect of immigration. No doubt they have their reasons. Who among them witnessed anything like the global refugee crisis of 2015? Or the anxieties about national identity that it inflamed? Be that as it may, with hostility toward immigrants and refugees fueling the "Brexit" movement and the presidential campaign of Donald Trump, we could use some deep thinking about the relationship between the state and its citizens.
On the case is the political philosopher David Miller. His book Strangers in Our Midst: The Political Philosophy of Immigration aims to be the first to combine such an abstract approach to the topic with such a strong dose of realism. Make no mistake: Mr Miller is a humane, social democratic Oxford University professor. But comes down in favour of a state's right - except when human rights are threatened - to close its borders to outsiders, and proposes four principles that should govern policies while admitting immigrants.
The first principle is what he calls "weak cosmopolitanism." A weak cosmopolitan believes in the equal worth of all human beings but sees this as morally compatible with giving special consideration to our compatriots. The argument is simple: The radical changes to our behaviour required by a strong cosmopolitanism - which holds that we have an obligation to treat all people the same - would entail abandoning too much of what gives shape and meaning to our lives.
In the context of immigration, strong cosmopolitanism mandates an international "open borders" policy, whereas weak cosmopolitanism dictates only that a country's policy cannot violate anyone's human rights and sometimes must actively protect them.
Mr Miller's second principle is national self-determination. Immigration can bring about considerable change to a country, and Mr Miller argues that citizens have the right to decide whether such changes would bolster or undermine their society. Any such policies have to be consistent with weak cosmopolitanism - and also, Mr Miller believes, with his third principle: fairness. The aim of a state's immigration policy has to be one that would-be immigrants ought to accept as reasonable.
Does that seem as if it might get blurry in practice? The early history of immigration policy in America, as told by historian Douglas C Baynton in Defectives In The Land: Disability And Immigration In The Age Of Eugenics suggests so. Traditionally, scholars have divided that history into two periods: a "selective" phase starting in 1882, which involved screening out individuals with any "defect" that would render them "likely to become a public charge"; and a "restrictive phase" starting with the passage of a literacy test in 1917.
Yet Mr Baynton, challenging conventional historiography, argues that the selective phase, despite its reliance on the "public charge" standard, was no less discriminatory. During those years, he demonstrates, immigration officials could and did customarily invoke this to rule out such "defectives" as women unaccompanied by male providers and members of races with supposed "predispositions" to criminality.
The fourth of Mr Miller's principles is social integration, where Mr Miller calls for certain commitments, as well as a certain flexibility, on the part of everyone involved.
Mr Miller argues for reciprocity with respect to cultural integration. A Muslim immigrant to Italy, he feels, should not object to the presence of a crucifix in his daughter's classroom as a symbol of the nation's Catholic heritage; but neither should her school object to her preference for modest dress and the wearing of a head scarf. Here, too, the American example is relevant. In his minutely detailed City Of Gods the historian R Scott Hanson uses the story of Flushing - which calls itself the birthplace of religious freedom in America and is now the hub of the most religiously diverse large county in the US - as a "case study" of the promises and drawbacks of pluralism. How religiously diverse can a society get?
Mr Hanson, who has also done ethnographic work in the neighbourhood, concludes there is virtually "no limit" to how much religious diversity a society can accommodate. But he also finds that when it comes to cooperation and unity - two goals that Mr Miller, at least, places considerable emphasis on - there are limits to how much of a sense of community you can achieve in such a pluralistic environment. It's another consideration to bear in mind for those who seek to respect social cohesion as well as the rights and interests of prospective immigrants.
©2016 The New York Times News service